Skip to main content

Reassessing the approach to informed consent: the case of unrelated hematopoietic stem cell transplantation in adult thalassemia patients

Abstract

Introduction

The informed consent process is the legal embodiment of the fundamental right of the individual to make decisions affecting his or her health., and the patientā€™s permission is a crucial form of respect of freedom and dignity, it becomes extremely important to enhance the patientā€™s understanding and recall of the information given by the physician. This statement acquires additional weight when the medical treatment proposed can potentially be detrimental or even fatal. This is the case of thalassemia patients pertaining to class 3 of the Pesaro classification where Allogenic hematopoietic stem cell transplantation (HSCT) remains the only potentially curative treatment. Unfortunately, this kind of intervention is burdened by an elevated transplantation-related mortality risk (TRM: all deaths considered related to transplantation), equal to 30% according to published reports. In thalassemia, the role of the patient in the informed consent process leading up to HSCT has not been fully investigated. This study investigated the hypothesis that information provided by physicians in the medical scenario of HSCT is not fully understood by patients and that misunderstanding and communication biases may affect the clinical decision-making process.

Methods

A questionnaire was either mailed or given personally to 25 patients. A second questionnaire was administered to the 12 physicians attending the patients enrolled in this study. Descriptive statistics were used to evaluate the communication factors.

Results

The results pointed out the difference between the risks communicated by physicians and the risks perceived by patients. Besides the study highlighted the mortality risk considered to be acceptable by patients and that considered to be acceptable by physicians.

Conclusions

Several solutions have been suggested to reduce the gap between communicated and perceived data. A multi-disciplinary approach may possibly help to attenuate some aspects of communication bias. Several tools have also been proposed to fill or to attenuate the gap between communicated and perceived data. But the most important tool is the ability of the physician to comprehend the right place of conscious consent in the relationship with the patient.

Introduction

There is worldwide agreement that principle of informed consent is intended to reflect the concept of patientsā€™ autonomy and self-determination and to be the legal embodiment of the right of each individual to make decisions about his or her own health care [1]. In Italy, the legal basis for informed consent is well established by article 32 of the Italian Constitution that asserts that patients cannot be forced to submit to a medical treatment, unless the treatment is required by law. However, if the need to respect the patientā€™s autonomy and its contribution to the good of the patient are not well understood, this unquestionable right of patients cannot be properly respected. We contend that obligations arising from moral or legislative precepts do not adequately reflect the true value of informed consent.

The importance of informed consent is habitually stressed by several scholars referring to a quote of 1914 by Justice Cardozo that states: Ā«Every human being of adult years and sound mind has a right to determine what shall be done with his own body; and a surgeon who performs an operation without his patientā€™s consent commits an assault, for which he is liable in damagesĀ» [2]. But a true interpretation of informed consent actually dates back as far as 1895, when George Surbled stated that Ā«patients have the right to refuse any kind of trial or therapy merely barricading themselves behind their wish without any justifications. In fact they are the only masters of their life, then of their body that they can use as they likeĀ» [3]. This statement acquires additional weight when the proposed medical treatment may potentially be detrimental or even fatal. But what should inspire the concept of informed consent? By honor of their profession, physicians have the moral responsibility to identify reasonable treatment options for each patient and then to discuss with them the benefits and potential risks of these treatment options, answer their questions as openly and honestly as possible to identify the option they feel is most appropriate and finally to accept the patientā€™s choice (so long as they can do so in good conscience). The fundamental goal of this long procedure that consists in transmitting the information and obtaining informed consent, is to ensure that patients, are fully aware and conscious both of the natural threats of their disease and of the potential possibilities of recovery. The true essence of informed consent is to transfer the knowledge of the risks and benefits from the one who knows them (namely, the physician) to the one who has to go through and experience them (the patient). Since Ī²-Thalassemia major is a disorder in which this challenge is particularly relevant, mutual understanding among physicians and patients is essential in this process.

Thalassemia

Ī²-thalassemia is a severe hereditary haemolytic anaemia that arises from the reduced or absent synthesis of the haemoglobin subunit beta. Clinical findings include severe anaemia, hepatic fibrosis and cirrhosis, diabetes mellitus, hypogonadism, growth retardation, sexual immaturity, moderate to severe pulmonary syndromes and cardiac disorders. Myocardial disease is by far the most important life-limiting complication and is responsible for about 70 percent of deaths in these patients [4].

Allogenic hematopoietic stem cell transplantation (HSCT) remains the only potentially curative treatment [5]. On the other hand, transfusion and iron chelation therapies are a valid alternative in patients who are compliant with treatment recommendations. In fact, the availability of better treatment strategies has considerably improved the survival and complication-free survival rates in these patients [6ā€“8].

Unfortunately, unrelated HSCT in thalassemia patients pertaining to the class 3 of the Pesaro classification (mostly adult patients with presence of hepatomegaly, portal fibrosis and a history of irregular iron chelation) is burdened by a high transplantation-related mortality risk (TRM: all deaths that are considered to be associated with transplantation), equal to 30% according to published reports [9ā€“11]. Graft versus Host Disease (GVHD), i.e. a reaction of donated bone marrow against the patientā€™s own tissue, is a major cause of post-transplantation morbidity and mortality but, although the use of new protocols has consistently reduced the risk of toxicity, the percentage of TRM is still high [12]. Hence, patients without an HLA-identical sibling donor are left with the difficult choice of whether they should continue traditional therapy, which can offer a life expectancy of fifteen years or more, or accept the high risk of unrelated HSCT in the hope of definitively eradicating the disease. This latter point marks the fundamental difference between thalassemia and other diseases, such as leukemia or myeloma, which are characterized by their unfavorable prognosis and the lack of an alternative to HSCT [13].

It is well known that in medicine it is mandatory for patients and physicians to thoroughly discuss the advantages, limits, and complications of the all so far available potentially effective therapeutic approaches. Indeed, several clinical reports have stressed the importance of communication strategies and of their introduction into routine medical practice [14, 15]. This study combines the results of unrelated HSCT, performed in 34 adult class 3 thalassemia patients, with the main communication factors between patients and physicians. In thalassemia the role of the patient in the informed consent process leading up to HSCT has not been fully investigated so far.

We decided to evaluate whether communication biases, heuristics, distorted processes of recall and misunderstanding could affect the clinical decision-making process and compromise the informed consent process for unrelated HSCT. We also address the legal and deontological issues with particular emphasis on the physician-patient healing relationship and the moral aspects of clinical decision-making. Informing patients of all the factors involved in their health care is the primary responsibility of the physician who can thereby guarantee a more ā€œself-awareā€ informed consent process to patients.

We hypothesized that the information provided by physicians in the medical scenario of HSCT might not be fully understood by patients and that misunderstanding and communication biases may affect the clinical decision-making process. Several errors in judgment may cause bias in communication between patients and physicians. Under a condition of uncertainty or in case of high risk, human beings are prone to take mental shortcuts commonly known as ā€œheuristicsā€. Cognitive psychologists have categorized several heuristics: availability (tendency to judge an event by the ease with which relevant examples are recalled), anchoring (to use an initial piece of information to make subsequent judgments); framing effects (to reach a decision based on the ā€˜frameworkā€™ within which the information was given); blind obedience (to indiscriminately follow the decision of an authority) [16]. Heuristics are commonly used by patients within the informed consent process and they seem to be at least partly responsible for the discordance observed between the perceptions of patients and their treating physicians with regard to the risks and benefits of treatment [17].

Methods

Thirty-four consecutive adult class 3 thalassemic patients (16 males and 18 females) aged more than 16Ā years (median 21, range 16 - 37) were transplanted from an unrelated donor after a myeloablative regimen in two different Italian bone marrow transplantation centers. Patientsā€™ clinical features are shown in TableĀ 1. Every informed consent session and all the information provided to patients were fully documented to get a realistic picture of the meeting. All the physicians involved collected and discussed in advance literature data on GVHD and mortality risk rates during a consensus conference. The analysis of the informed consent process was conducted on the 25 surviving patients (12 males and 13 females) after obtaining a written informed consent from them or from their parents in the case of children under the age of 18Ā years. A questionnaire was either emailed or given personally to patients. A second questionnaire was administered to the 12 physicians who treated the patients enrolled in this study. Written informed consent was provided by the patients according to the Declaration of Helsinki. The study was approved by the Ethics Board of the University of Cagliari, School of Medicine.

Table 1 Patient features

Questionnaires

The questionnaires were developed in collaboration with a multidisciplinary team including an expert psychologist, surgeons and nurses. Physicians and patients were asked to recall the time when they respectively informed and were informed for the first time of the possibility of unrelated HSCT. The questionnaire that was administered both to physicians and patients contained the following 6 items, assessed with the visual 7 item Likert-type scale or percent values (TableĀ 2): 1) the transplant-related mortality risk perception on a seven-item Likert-type scale; 2) the mortality risk rate communicated by the physician and recalled by the patients (this item was intended to detect whether there was a possible frame effect between numeric variables provided by the physicians and those recalled by the patients); 3) the percent value of mortality risk that was considered acceptable to undergo the transplant procedure; 4) the perception of GVHD as a life-threatening condition; 5) how much previous additional information (from family, friends with thalassemia, TV, internet etc.) had influenced the choice of undergoing HSCT (this item allowed to detect a potential availability heuristic); 6) the strength of the patientā€™s motivation to undergo HSCT before the informed consent session with the physician (this item allowed to detect an eventual anchoring heuristic).

Table 2 Communication factors explored among patients and physicians

The information was conveyed by the physician with the aid of numeric values such as a percentage or by showing Kaplan Meyer overall survival and TRM curves previously published in literature. In order to verify the results of the informed consent session over time, we wrote them all, e.g. failure and death rates, in a case history. These notes helped us compare the real rates the patients were told with the rates the patients remembered.

Statistical analysis

Descriptive statistics were used to evaluate communication factors. The data we collected were summarized by reporting the proportion of patients answering each item. Association between patient preferences and demographical characteristics was evaluated by logistic regression analysis. Different groups were compared using the t-test for independent samples. Post-transplant survival probability was estimated using the Kaplan and Meier method [18].

Results

Clinical outcome

The Kaplan-Meier survival and TRM probabilities for the 34 patients studied were 73.5% and 26.5% respectively. Nine patients died of transplantation-related causes at a mean time of 170Ā days (range 17-470) after the HSCT procedure. Six of these patients presented acute GVHD (67%). Among the 25 surviving, transfusion-independent patients, 3 (12%) developed grade II-IV acute GVHD and 3 (12%) developed mild chronic GVHD. The median follow-up of surviving patients was 5.9Ā years (range 0.9-8.4).

Questionnaires

The 25 surviving transfusion-independent patients returned the questionnaire after a median of 20Ā days, with answers to all the 6 items. The median time between HSCT and the survey was 12Ā months. The median age of patients at the time of the survey was 25Ā years (range 18-35). All the 12 treating physicians involved in the informed consent and in the clinical decision-making process completed the questionnaire. TableĀ 3 shows the score differences between physicians and patients.

Table 3 Differences between patients and physicians perceptions

The mortality risk perceived by the patients, assessed on a 7-item Likert scale, was significantly lower if compared to the risk perceived by the physicians (3.6 vs 4.9, pā€‰=ā€‰0.001). The mean mortality risk rate that was actually communicated by the physicians was 30%, while the rate that was later recalled among the patients was significantly lower (20%). No demographic features influenced the patientā€™s recall of the mortality risk rate. Interestingly, the mortality risk that was considered to be acceptable by the physicians was significantly lower compared to the mortality risk that was considered to be acceptable by the patients (19.6 vs 29.6, pā€‰=ā€‰0.005). Among patients, this rate was significantly lower in the female patients than in the male ones (25% vs 34%, pā€‰=ā€‰0.003).

The perception of the risk of GVHD as a life-threatening condition (assessed on a 7-item Likert scale) was again significantly lower among the patients if compared to physicians (4.1 vs 5.4, pā€‰=ā€‰0.006). Female patients perceived a higher risk than male patients (5.2 vs 3.1, pā€‰=ā€‰0.024). The other demographic features that were analyzed such as the age or the level of education had no influence on the patientā€™s perception of severe GVHD as a life-threatening condition.

Finally, patients were strongly self-motivated to undergo HSCT before the informed consent process (4.8 on a 7 seven-item Likert-type scale). According to physiciansā€™ evaluation, patients had been strongly influenced by information they had previously obtained from non-professional sources (4.6 on a 7 seven-item Likert-type scale).

Discussion

The majority of therapies expose patients to some degree of risk. In fact, the beneficial effects of drugs and therapeutic approaches are always counterbalanced by undesired consequences. Therefore, it becomes essential for the physician and the patient to discuss beforehand the appropriateness of cure and/or treatment options, in order to achieve the patientā€™s best interest. (The) Physician must be able to balance beneficence and maleficence when considering the feasibility of treatment. Exploration of communication strategies between physicians and patients/relatives may lead to a better understanding of the factors that play a prominent role in the consent and in its comprehension. In general, patients who are satisfied with communication can cope with treatment-related stress better. Several authors emphasize the importance of imparting individually tailored information. In seeking consent, physicians must supply patients and/or participants with an adequate amount of information but, more importantly, they must make sure that the information has been fully understood [19, 20]. The degree and the quality of information that should be disclosed to the patient represent a key question. A recent Cochrane review [21] identified ā€˜efforts by researchers to investigate interventions which seek to improve information delivery and consideration of information to enhance informed consent. although we were not able to say with confidence which types of interventions are preferableā€™. A common approach in the legal and bioethical community seems to consider either spontaneous, that is the information given spontaneously in spoken, written or video form and responsive disclosure, that comprises the information given in response to the patientā€™s questions [22]. In this model, widely adopted also in the Italian wards, a dual procedural aim is reached. The patient-physician relationship may rely on one side on the standard medical information a reasonable person may need to make the decision in question, while on the other hand the physician may enrich the information on the basis of the individual patient needs and doubts (in a tailored information protocol).

Although the number of patients involved in our study is robust enough to depict the entire phenomenon (25% of the Italian Pesaro class-3 transplanted patients with Ī²-Thalassemia Major), (it) is not sufficient to draw a definitive conclusion. Despite this, we believe that our experience can be significant and instructive in the field of hematology to better understand the importance of informed consent in the patient-physician relationship.

The non-standardization and the non-psychometrical validation of the questionnaires used in the study is another potential limitation of our study. The Cochrane review [21] underlines that high levels of heterogeneity associated with many of the main analyses may encourage the meta-analysis results to be interpreted with caution and these limits are present in the vast majority of studies on informed consent. In fact, as we needed to assess our patients in a short time and no validated questionnaires allowing evaluation of the patientsā€™ ability to recall the information provided during the informed consent process in this particular field of hematology were available, we decided not to undertake a validation process that would have required a long time.

Three issues of crucial importance need to be stressed at this point: 1 ā€“ the different way physicians and patients communicate and perceive risk; 2 ā€“ the different ways physicians and patients determine which level of risk is acceptable; 3 ā€“ the nonprofessional sources influencing the decision-making process.

Discrepancy between doctors and patients

Communicated and perceived risks

The data obtained in this study confirmed a clear difference in the communication and in the perception of HSCT-related risks among the patients and the physicians involved in the clinical relationship. Patients recalled a mortality risk rate that was lower than the mortality risk rate they were actually told by the physicians (20% vs 30%). It is interesting to observe that female patients were more aware of the potential risks of the procedure. There may be several reasons for this miscomprehension. It is possible that during the informed process, patients felt anxious because of the uncertainty of the clinical outcome, and were therefore prone to anchor their choice to personal hope or to an initially positive impression. In fact, patientsā€™ motivation to undergo HSCT before the discussion with the physician was very high (mean value of 4.6 on a 1-7 item Likert scale). Nevertheless, the questionnaires could not confirm a role for ā€œavailability heuristicsā€ (mean value of 2.2 on a 1-7 item Likert scale). This discordance may be partly attributed to the way in which physicians assessed the benefits and risks of HSCT. Indeed, when physicians present HSCT in terms of chances of survival (positive frame), they paint a scenery that is psychologically much more acceptable than it would be if the procedure were proposed in terms of chances of death (negative trend). Ideally, a balance of both negative and positive views should be always presented [23]. Physicians not only have to improve their communication skills [24], but they also have to be sure that patients can remember in the best possible way the information provided during the consent process [25].

Patientā€™s recollection plays a fundamental role in the informed consent process: ordinary recollection processes may lead to distortions of crucial information, but even, patients may misremember information gained, due to different attitude toward the weighing information process before and after their decision. It has been shown that patients are likely to forget information based on verbatim memory (i.e. risks and complications rates), and to ground their choice on gist memory, which reflects enduring understanding and interpretation [26]. Unfortunately, informed consent is generally based on the communication of data, numbers and/or rates. In recent years, there has been a revolution in communication strategies. Manual information systems have increasingly been integrated by computer-based technologies capable of implementing the quality of communication. In particular, visual communication has been shown to be extremely effective in strengthening communication [23, 27]: indeed, the majority of people seem to find it easier to remember pictures than words. However, these efforts were generally not so successful or showed mixed results in some patients [28]. Other strategies like corrected feedback, as Festinger et al suggest, may improve the recall of information, but the time interval required to realize this procedure is too long to be used in unrelated hematopoietic stem cell transplantation [29]. Surely, by improving our knowledge of the various communication strategies as visual graphs, movies, alternative formats to present and frame risk information- it may be possible to attenuate some of the current biases encountered within the decision-making process with the patient. However, we also have to investigate or assess the responsibility of the physician within the communication process, above all his/her understanding of the real role of informed consent in the relationship with the patient.

Acceptability of risk

Our results show that there is a significant difference comparing the acceptability of mortality risk in physicians and patients, i.e. 20% and 30% respectively, and comparing female and male patients, with the former being more realistic (34% vs. 25%). A higher mortality risk is likely to be accepted more easily by people with a serious and chronic disease than healthy individuals as the former have a stronger motivation to recover. This kind of reactions is not only comprehensible, but even acceptable. The way people react to illness was studied by Elisabeth Kubler Ross who indicated acceptance as the last stage and denial/refusal as the first one [30]. Diseases change the way people perceive illness and disease-related risks. In fact, if there is a real possibility of recovery, people suffering from a disease are disposed to accept high risks and severe side effects differently from healthy individuals. Therefore physicians have to be aware that patients perceive their disease and disease-related risks differently from them and that they should not conduct the informed consent process subjectively, but only focusing on scientific evidence.

Influences in decision making

Another intriguing item that emerged from our analysis concerns the moment at which patients take their therapeutic decision. Our results show that patients are strongly persuaded to undergo HSCT before starting the informed consent process. During the information process this event may undermine patient attentiveness to the information provided by physician, and undermine physicians motivation to provide detail if the physician believes that the patient has already made his/her decision. At a more in-depth analysis, a medical choice made by patients before they are provided with all the necessary information by their treating physician, albeit legal and acceptable threatens, the medical role of a ā€˜trusted guide on the illness journeyā€™ [22]. The ratio of the information process relies on the need to bridge the knowledge gap between physician and patient, due to the cultural difference existing on the knowledge of medical issues. The main aim of the informed consent process is to give the patient all the scientific tools that are necessary to let him/her freely and deliberately decide for his/her own good. What if the physician is not longer identified (anymore) as the trusted scientific source of the ā€˜gold standardā€™ in information and treatment? Do physicians have a (the) duty to respect the patientā€™s therapeutic choice or refusal, even when such choices are not grounded in an accurate understanding of verified or validated assessment (their technical evaluation) of the available and shared medical protocols, as was the case in the recent Italian debate on FDA/EMA/AIFA unauthorized protocol (proposed by the Stamina Foundation) on the therapeutic use of stem cells? May naĆÆve suggestions (or misinformation) coming from the web or from other questionable sources supplant a sound medical information process? In such scenario, a patientā€™s autonomy and a physicianā€™s of beneficence both appear to be threatened and finding a shared decision making process becomes imperative.

Consent: precious or unnecessary?

Our observations show that the consent process is not a mere bureaucratic procedure and that physicians should emphasize its importance more forcefully [31]. In fact, informed consent is sometimes considered as a bureaucratic burden or a legal myth [32], or even as an ineffective signing procedure [33], that regrettably continues to be used in a paternalistic way by some healthcare professionals [34]. Some physicians also use informed consent as a method of defensive medicine to protect themselves and not to preserve patients and their own dignity [35].

Conversely physicians should foster the patient-physician relationship and implement the informed consent process that entail respecting patientsā€™ autonomy, acting for their good and empowering them to make decisions in line with their own values. On the other side patientsā€™ decision may be grounded in unscientific and irrational basis even when the physician has provided them with accurate information.

All the issues that have been analyzed so far seem to cast doubts on the fundamental basis of the informed consent doctrine. A deep gap between the quality and the quantity of the clinical information provided by physicians and the one gathered and recalled by patients has been demonstrated. If these data are representative of a more general phenomenon, all the legal and ethical considerations on the fundamental basis of consent lose their importance. The clinical decision to undergo or to refuse the HSCT treatment is taken apart from the relevant issues concerning procedural security and personal values.

The validity of individual consent resides in the physicianā€™s ability to convey exhaustive and essential information and, (contemporarily, depends upon) in the patientā€™s ability to properly interact with the doctor that will allow him/her to fully understand and recall the information provided. Before seeking the patientā€™s agreement, the physician has the fundamental duty to inform the patient completely and to make sure that he or she is aware of, and has genuinely understood, the risks and benefits both of the proposed treatment [36] and of alternative procedures and treatments. A new advance in the informed consent process can be approachable only in a new and right equilibrium between the pursuit of beneficence and reverence for autonomy.

Beneficence, autonomy and self-aware consent

Over the last 50Ā years, patient(ā€™s) freedom has become the hallmark of the patient-physician relationship, while beneficence has progressively lost the central position it had held in the past.

Precisely, the shift from beneficence to autonomy introduced a new approach to clinical decision-making that led to the doctrine of informed consent. Today, autonomy is widely considered to be one of the four master principles of bioethics and plays a prominent role in the medical setting. However, although the recognition of the value of autonomy has certainly been one of the most important achievements in the field of bioethics so far, autonomy and beneficence should not be considered separately as Beauchamp and Childress contend [37], or as contrasting principles, as Engelhardt asserts [38].

In our opinion, the concept of autonomy should not be considered as an independent principle and beneficence should not be identified with paternalism as Will maintained [31]. In fact, they are both cornerstones of the doctrine of informed consent, and beneficence cannot be achieved if patientā€™s autonomy is not respected.

The importance of autonomy is therefore closely related to the principle of beneficence. In fact, the good of the patient cannot be achieved if patients are not supported in their right to autonomous choice. Then, it is mandatory to consider autonomy as an unavoidable condition to attain the good and not a principle beside beneficence. Hence, beneficence and autonomy are inseparable concepts, but not inseparable principles, essentially because autonomy is not a principle [33]. Pellegrino and Thomasma successfully emphasized the principle of beneficence, but they have never challenged the idea of autonomy as a principle [39]. From our point of view, informed consent becomes an indisputable means to support autonomy, in order to achieve beneficence [40ā€“42]. However, only beneficence can be recognized as a principle.

Consent was initially designed not only to preserve patientsā€™ independence during the decision-making process [31], but also to allow physicians to act for the good of patients by promoting their understanding and, consequently, their right to choose or refuse the proposed treatment freely.

In fact, the good of patients cannot be achieved by a mere supply of information that may even be misleading in some cases. The term ā€œinformed consentā€ is itself so ambiguous that some authors have suggested to replace it with ā€œInformation for consensusā€, as in the Italian deontological medical code [31]. However, this expression is still unclear, as it does not entail patientsā€™ understanding during the consent process [43, 44]. In fact, physicians often provide patients with a large amount of information, but they donā€™t verify whether patients understand the key points of the conversation.

This observation has led us to shift from the concept of ā€œinformed consentā€ to the more appropriate one of ā€œself-aware consentā€ [45]. We are well aware of the debate around consciousness, that led several authors to stress the importance on the unconscious events arising from the patient-physician relationship. In particular, scholars who identify mental events with brain events are inclined to consider the process of legal consent as an illusion or, even, as a myth [46]. In this article we have already stressed the importance of unconscious events but, at the same time, we are deeply convinced that a self-aware consent can be obtained if all the factors involved are taken into account. Actually, the pursuit of self-aware consent is paramount. While, on the one hand, consent implies the concepts of information and contextualization, on the other, it is awareness that plays the most crucial role in our opinion. For this reason, physicians must not only pay attention to all the factors that are important to obtain this goal, but they also must identify the subconscious and unconscious barriers as much as possible. In our opinion, that is not a burden, but a fascinating task that helps physicians respect and promote patientā€™ autonomy when trying to reach beneficence. We believe that patientsā€™ choice can be deliberately autonomous only if it is aware. In fact, autonomy and awareness are not correspondent: a decision could only apparently seem autonomous, and actually be not real aware.

We believe that the right way to build a correct procedure of consent must be searched in a sort of mediation between all of the factors involved in the relationship: the patientā€™s need to be respected in his/her autonomy and freedom and, at the same time, the doctorā€™s need to be recognized in his/her moral integrity and knowledge in the field.

The goal is to reach a real empowerment of the patient to be part of a shared-decision making model [47] in which ā€˜a patient may take some responsibility for her or his own health care rather than merely being loaded with a great deal of complex informationā€™ [22]. In this context physicians could provide their patient with moral recommendations about his/her responsibility without becoming necessarily paternalistic.

We agree with Mazur who identifies at least six dimensions in the decision-making process that should be taken into account by the physicians involved in HSCT procedures: harms, benefits, scientific evidence, clinical experience, estimation experience and psychological experience involving estimates [48]. In our opinion, another dimension, i.e. self-aware consent, should be added. Self-aware consent is a valid procedure only at the time that the patient is giving consent; in fact, if some conditions are going to change, i.e. clinical picture, environmental conditions, consent must be reconsidered. Indeed, consent is somehow a dynamic procedure that portrays a specific situation at an established moment rather than a static process given once and for all.

Conclusions

Self-aware consent is crucial in the patient-physician relationship and its achievement can be affected by several dilemmas. A multi-disciplinary approach (medical, psychological and ethical) may possibly help to smooth some of the challenging issues characterizing the information procedure. Several ways have been suggested to fill or attenuate the gap between communicated and perceived information, but physiciansā€™ ability to value the informed consent within their relationship with patients undoubtedly plays a key role [21]. The pursuit of self-aware consent is paramount and physicians have to realize that respecting patientsā€™ freedom is part of the goal of their profession and that self-aware consent in a shared-decision making model rather than informed consent is the only ground where freedom can be respected.

Abbreviations

HSCT:

Allogenic Hematopoietic Stem Cell Transplantation

GVHD:

Graft Versus Host Disease

TRM:

Transplantation-Related Mortality.

References

  1. Paterick TJ, Carson GU, Allen MC, Paterick TE: Medical informed consent: general considerations for physicians. Mayo Clin Proc. 2008, 83: 313-319. 10.4065/83.3.313

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  2. Schloendorff vv the society of the New York Hospital: 1914, 211 NY 125 105 NE 92 1914 Lexis 1028,

  3. Surbled G: La Morale dans ses Rapports avec la Medicine et lā€™Hygiene. 1905, 216-217. Paris: V. Retaux et fils,

    Google ScholarĀ 

  4. Rund D, Rachmilewtz E: Beta thalassemia. New Engl J Med. 2005, 353: 1135-1146. 10.1056/NEJMra050436

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  5. Borgna-Pignatti C, Rugolotto S, De Stefano P, Zhoo H, Cappellini MD, Del Vecchio GC, Romeo MA, Forni GL, Gamberini MR, Ghilardi R, Piga A, Cuccu A: Marrow transplantation in patients with thalassemia major treated with transfusion and deferoxamine. Haematologica. 2004, 89: 1187-1193.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  6. Borgna Pignatti C, Rugolotto S, De Stefano P, Piga A, Di Gregorio F, Gamberini MR, Sabato U, Melevendi C, Cappellini MD, Verlato G: Survival and disease complications in thalassemia major. Ann New York Acad Sci. 1998, 850: 227-231. 10.1111/j.1749-6632.1998.tb10479.x. 10.1111/j.1749-6632.1998.tb10479.x

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  7. Taher A, Jefri A, Elalfly MS, Al Zir K, Daar S, Rofail D, Baladi JF, Habr D, Kriemler-Krahn U, El-Beshlawy A: Improved treatment satisfaction and convenience with deferasirox in iron-overloaded patients with beta thalassemia: results from the ESCALATOR trial. Acta Haematol. 2010, 123: 220-225. 10.1159/000313447

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  8. Cao A, Galanello R: Beta Thalassemia. Genet Med. 2010, 12: 61-76. 10.1097/GIM.0b013e3181cd68ed

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  9. La Nasa G, Giarnini F, Colatelli F, Arras M, De Stefano P, Leda A, Pizzati A, Sanna MA, Vacca A, Lucarelli G, Contu L: Unrelated donor bone marrow transplantation for thalassemia: the effect of extended haplotypes. Blood. 2002, 99: 4350-4356. 10.1182/blood.V99.12.4350

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  10. Caocci G, Pisu S, Argioulu F, Giardini C, Locatelli F, Vacca A, Orofino MG, Piras E, De Stefano P, Addari MC, Ledda A, La Nasa G: Unrelated donor bone marrow transplantation in adult patients with thalassemia. Bone Marrow Transplant. 2006, 37: 165-169. 10.1038/sj.bmt.1705236

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  11. Locatelli F: Outcome of unrelated donor bone marrow transplantation for thalassemia major patients [abstract]. Blood. 2011, 118: 149-10.1182/blood-2011-06-362053. 10.1182/blood-2011-06-362053

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  12. Bernardo ME, Piras E, Vacca A, Giorgiani G, Zecca M, Bertaina A, Pagliara D, Contoli B, Pinto RM, Caocci G, Mastronuzzi A, La Nasa G, Locatelli F: Allogeneic hematopoietic stem cell transplantation in thalassemia major: results of a reduced-toxicity conditioning regimen based on the use of treosulfan. Blood. 2012, 120: 473-476. 10.1182/blood-2012-04-423822

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  13. Merckaert I, Libert Y, Bron D, Jaivenois MF, Martiat P, Slachmuyalder JL, Razavi D: Impact of life-threatening risk information on the evolution of patientā€™ anxiety and risk recall: the specific context of informed consent for experimental stem cell transplant. Patient Educ Couns. 2009, 75: 192-198. 10.1016/j.pec.2008.09.013

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  14. Mazur DJ, Hickam DH: Patientsā€™ preferences for risk disclosure and role in decision making for invasive medical procedures. J Gen Intern Med. 1997, 12: 114-117. 10.1007/s11606-006-5006-8

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  15. Kerr J, Engel J, Schlesinger-Raab A, Sauer H, Holzel D: Communication, quality of life and age: results of a 5Ā year prospective study in breast cancer patients. Ann Oncol. 2003, 14: 421-427. 10.1093/annonc/mdg098

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  16. Redelmeier DA: The cognitive psychology of missed diagnoses. Ann Intern Med. 2005, 142: 115-120.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  17. Meropol NJ, Weinfurt KP, Burnett CB, Balshem A, Benson AB, Castel L, Corbett S, Diefenbach M, Gaskin D, Li Y, Manne S, Marshall J, Rowland JH, Slater E, Sulmasy DP, Van Echo D, Washinfion S, Schulman KA: Perceptions of patients and physician regarding phase-1 cancer clinical trials: implications for physician-patient communication. J Clin Oncol. 2003, 21: 2589-2596. 10.1200/JCO.2003.10.072

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  18. Kaplan ER, Meier P: Non parametric estimation from incomplete observation. J Am Stat Assoc. 1958, 53: 457-481. 10.1080/01621459.1958.10501452. 10.1080/01621459.1958.10501452

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  19. Schofield PE, Butow PN, Thompson JF, Tattersall MH, Beeney LJ, Dunn SM: Psychological responses of patients receiving a diagnosis of cancer. Ann Oncol. 2003, 14: 48-56. 10.1093/annonc/mdg010

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  20. Ptacek JT, Eberhardt TL: The patient-physician relationship. Breaking bad news: a review of the literature. J Am Med Assoc. 1996, 276: 492-496. 10.1001/jama.1996.03540060068039. 10.1001/jama.1996.03540060068039

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  21. Kinnersley P, Philips K, Savage K, Kelly MJ, Farrell E, Morgan B, Whistance R, Lewis V, Mann MK, Stephens BL, Blazeby J, Elwyn G, Edwards AGK: Interventions to promote informed consent for patients undergoing surgical and other invasive healthcare procedures (review). Cochrane Libr. 2013, CD009445-7,

    Google ScholarĀ 

  22. Gillett G, Walker S: The evolution of informed consent. J Law Med. 2012, 19 (4): 673-677.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  23. Paling J: Strategies to help patients understand risk. Br Med J. 2003, 327: 745-748. 10.1136/bmj.327.7417.745. 10.1136/bmj.327.7417.745

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  24. Elwyn G, Edwards A, Gwyn R, Grol R: Towards a feasible model for shared decision making: focus group with general practice registrars. Br Med J. 1999, 319: 753-756. 10.1136/bmj.319.7212.753. 10.1136/bmj.319.7212.753

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  25. Sardell AN, Trierweiler SJ: Disclosing the cancer diagnosis. Procedures that influence patient hopefulness. Cancer. 1997, 72: 3355-3365.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  26. Reyna VF, Hamilton AJ: The importance of memory in informed consent for surgical risk. Med Decis Making. 2001, 21: 152-155. 10.1177/0272989X0102100209

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  27. Fortin JM, Hirota LK, Bond BE, Oā€™Cobbor AM, Col NF: Identifying patient preferences for communicating risk estimates: a descriptive pilot study. BMC Med Inform Decis Mak. 2001, 1: 2- 10.1186/1472-6947-1-2

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  28. Agre P, Kurtz RC, Krauss BJ: A randomized trial using videotape to present consent information from colonoscopy. Gastrointest Endosc. 1994, 40: 271-276. 10.1016/S0016-5107(94)70054-0

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  29. Festinger DS, Dugosh KL, Croft JR, Arabia PL, Marlowe DB: Corrected feedback: a procedure to enhance recall of informed consent to research among substance abusing offenders. Ethics Behav. 2010, 20 (5): 387-399. 10.1080/10508422.2010.491767

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  30. Kubler Ross E: On Death and Dying. 1973, London UK: Routledge,

    Google ScholarĀ 

  31. Mallardi V: The origin of informed consent. Acta Otorhinolaryngol Ital. 2005, 25: 312-327.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  32. Laforet EG: The fiction of informed consent. J Am Med Assoc. 1997, 235: 1579-1584.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  33. Devettere RJ: Pratical Decision Making in Health Care Ethics. 2000, 99-100. Washington D.C: Georgetown University Press,

    Google ScholarĀ 

  34. Will JF: A brief historical and theoretical perspective on patient autonomy and medical decision making. Chest. 2011, 139 (3): 669-673. 10.1378/chest.10-2532

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  35. Shorter E: The troubled history of doctors and patients. 1985, New York: Simon and Shuster ed,

    Google ScholarĀ 

  36. Sreenivasan G: Does informed consent to research require comprehension?. Lancet. 2003, 362: 2016-2018. 10.1016/S0140-6736(03)15025-8

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  37. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF: Principles of Biomedical Ethics. 2009, New York-Oxford: Oxford University Press,

    Google ScholarĀ 

  38. Engelhardt HT: The foundations of Bioethics. 1996, New York-Oxford: Oxford University Press,

    Google ScholarĀ 

  39. Pellegrino ED, Thomasma D: For the Patient Good. The Restoration of Beneficence in Health Care. 1988, New York-Oxford: Oxford University Press,

    Google ScholarĀ 

  40. Caocci G, La Nasa G, dā€™Aloja E, Vacca A, Piras E, Pintor M, Demontis R, Pisu S: Ethical issues on unrelated hematopoietic stem cell transplantation in adult thalassemia patients. BMC Med Ethics. 2011, 12: 4- 10.1186/1472-6939-12-4

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  41. dā€™Aloja E, Pintor M, Paribello F, Pisu S: Neither freedom nor autonomy without beneficence. Arch Intern Med. 2008, 168: 548-549.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  42. Jacoby LH, Maloy B, Cirenza E, Shelton W, Goggins T, Balint J: The basis of informed consent for BMT patients. Bone Marrow Transplant. 1999, 23: 711-717. 10.1038/sj.bmt.1701631

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  43. Terri RF, Bradley EH, Towle VR, Allore H: Understanding the treatment preferences of seriously ill patients. New Engl J Med. 2002, 346: 1061-1066. 10.1056/NEJMsa012528

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  44. Lee SJ: Putting shared decision making into practice. ASH Education Book. 2002, 473-477.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  45. Pisu S, Caocci G, La Nasa G, De Stefano F: The Role of Consent in the Relationship between Physician and Patient. Decision Making on Medicine and Health Care. Edited by: Tolana PC. 2008, 1-5. New York: Nova Biomedical Books,

    Google ScholarĀ 

  46. Gillet G: Intention, autonomy, and brain events. Bioethics. 2009, 23 (6): 330-339. 10.1111/j.1467-8519.2009.01726.x

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  47. dā€™Aloja E, Floris L, Muller M, Birocchi F, Fanos V, Paribello F, Demontis R: Shared decision-making in neonatology: an utopia or an attainable goal?. J Matern Fetal Neonatal Med. 2010, 23 (3): 56-58.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  48. Mazur DJ: The new medical conversation. 2003, 99-100. Boston: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers,

    Google ScholarĀ 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to say thank to Samantha Pinna for refining the English language and style and for her professional assistance in writing the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding authors

Correspondence to Salvatore Pisu or Giovanni Caocci.

Additional information

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Authorsā€™ contributions

GLN and GC designed and coordinated the study, interpreted data and wrote the first draft; FE and GSC coordinated data analysis and interpretation; AV, EP, RL, MGO and CA recruited patients and administered survey instruments; ED addressed the ethical and legal aspects and helped draft the manuscript; RD, MP and MRP addressed the legal aspects; FD addressed the ethical aspects; SP addressed the ethical aspects and wrote the last version of the manuscript. All authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Authorsā€™ original submitted files for images

Below are the links to the authorsā€™ original submitted files for images.

Authorsā€™ original file for figure 1

Rights and permissions

This article is published under license to BioMed Central Ltd. This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly credited.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pisu, S., Caocci, G., dā€™Aloja, E. et al. Reassessing the approach to informed consent: the case of unrelated hematopoietic stem cell transplantation in adult thalassemia patients. Philos Ethics Humanit Med 9, 13 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1186/1747-5341-9-13

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/1747-5341-9-13

Keywords